DOI QR코드

DOI QR Code

FILTERS OF BE-ALGEBRAS WITH RESPECT TO A CONGRUENCE

  • RAO, M. SAMBASIVA (Department of Mathematics, MVGR College of Engineering)
  • 투고 : 2015.07.09
  • 심사 : 2015.09.11
  • 발행 : 2016.01.30

초록

Some properties of filters are studied with respect to a congru-ence of BE-algebras. The notion of θ-filters is introduced and these classes of filters are then characterized in terms of congruence classes. A bijection is obtained between the set of all θ-filters of a BE-algebra and the set of all filters of the respective BE-algebra of congruences classes.

키워드

1. Introduction

The notion of BE-algebras was introduced and extensively studied by H.S. Kim and Y.H. Kim in [5]. These classes of BE-algebras were introduced as a generalization of the class of BCK-algebras of K. Iseki and S. Tanaka [4]. Some properties of filters of BE-algebras were studied by S.S. Ahn and Y.H. Kim in [1]. In [8], the notion of normal filters is introduced in BE-algebras. In [2,3], S.S. Ahn and Y.H. So and K.S. So introduced the notion of ideals in BE-algebras and proved several characterizations of such ideals. Also they generalized the notion of upper sets in BE-algebras, and discussed some properties of the characterizations of generalized upper sets related to the structure of ideals in transitive and self-distributive BE-algebras. In 2012, S.S. Ahn, Y.H. Kim and J.M. Ko [1] introduced the notion of a terminal section of BE-algebras and derived some characterizations of commutative BE-algebras in terms of lattice ordered relations and terminal sections. Recently in 2015, J.H. Park and Y.H. Kim [7] studied the properties of intersectional soft implicative filters of BE-algebras. In [10], A. Walendziak discussed some relationships between congruence relations and normal filters of a BE-algebra.

In this paper, two operations are introduced one from the set of all filters of a BE-algebra into the algebra of filters of its congruence classes and the other from the algebra of filters of the congruence classes into the set of all filters of the given BE-algebra. Later, it is shown that their composition is a closure operator on the set of all filters of a BE-algebra. The concept of θ-filters is introduced in BE-algebras with respect to a congruence. The θ-filters are also characterized in terms of congruence classes. A set of equivalent conditions is derived for every filter of a BE-algebra to become a θ-filter. Finally, a bijection is obtained between the set of all θ-filters of a BE-algebra and the set of all filters of it’s algebra of congruence classes.

 

2. Preliminaries

In this section, we present certain definitions and results which are taken mostly from the papers [1], [5] and [8] for the ready reference of the reader.

Definition 2.1 ([5]). An algebra (X, ∗, 1) of type (2, 0) is called a BE-algebra if it satisfies the following properties:

(1) x ∗ x = 1,

(2) x ∗ 1 = 1,

(3) 1 ∗ x = x,

(4) x ∗ (y ∗ z) = y ∗ (x ∗ z) for all x, y, z ∈ X.

Theorem 2.2 ([5]). Let (X, ∗, 1) be a BE-algebra. Then we have the following:

(1) x ∗ (y ∗ x) = 1

(2) x ∗ ((x ∗ y) ∗ y)) = 1

We introduce a relation ≤ on a BE-algebra X by x ≤ y if and only if x∗y = 1 for all x, y ∈ X. A BE-algebra X is called self-distributive if x ∗ (y ∗ z) = (x ∗ y) ∗ (x ∗ z) for all x, y, z ∈ X. In any self-distributive BE-algebra, the set ⟨a⟩ = {x ∈ X | a ≤ x} = {x ∈ X | a ∗ x = 1} is the smallest filter containing the element a ∈ X which is known as the principal filter of X generated by a.

Definition 2.3 ([1]). Let (X, ∗, 1) be a BE-algebra. A non-empty subset F of X is called a filter of X if, for all x, y ∈ X, it satisfies the following properties:

(a) 1 ∈ F,

(b) x ∈ F and x ∗ y ∈ F imply that y ∈ F.

Definition 2.4 ([8]). Let (X, ∗, 1) be a BE-algebra. A non-empty subset F of X is called a normal filter of X if it satisfies the following properties:

(a) 1 ∈ F,

(b) x ∈ X and a ∈ F imply that x ∗ a ∈ F.

Definition 2.5 ([10]). Let (X, ∗, 1) be a BE-algebra. A binary relation θ on X is called a congruence on X if (x, y) ∈ θ and (z,w) ∈ θ imply that (x∗z, y∗w) ∈ θ for all x, y, z, w ∈ X.

For any congruence θ on a BE-algebra X, the quotient algebra X/θ = {[x]θ | x ∈ X}, where [x]θ is a congruence class of x modulo θ, is a BE-algebra with respect to the operation [x]θ ∗ [y]θ = [x ∗ y]θ for all x, y ∈ X.

 

3. θ-filter in BE-algebras

In this section, the notion of θ-filters is introduced in BE-algebras. A bijection is obtained between the set of all θ-filters of a BE-algebra and the set of all filters of the BE-algebra of all congruence classes. We first prove the following crucial result which play a vital role in the forth coming results.

Theorem 3.1. A non-empty subset F of a BE-algebra X is a filter of X if and only if it satisfies the following conditions for all x, y ∈ X.

(1) x ∈ F implies y ∗ x ∈ F.

(2) a, b ∈ F implies (a ∗ (b ∗ x)) ∗ x ∈ F.

Proof. Assume that F is a filter of X. Let x ∈ F. We have x ∗ (y ∗ x) = y ∗ (x ∗ x) = y ∗ 1 = 1 ∈ F. Since x ∈ F and F is a filter, we get that y ∗ x ∈ F. Let a, b ∈ F. Since a∗((a∗(b∗x))∗(b∗x)) = (a∗(b∗x))∗(a∗(b∗x)) = 1, we get that a ≤ ((a∗(b∗x))∗(b∗x)). Since a ∈ F, it yields that (a∗(b∗x))∗(b∗x) ∈ F. Hence b ∗ ((a ∗ (b ∗ x)) ∗ x) ∈ F. Since b ∈ F, it implies (a ∗ (b ∗ x)) ∗ x ∈ F.

Conversely, assume that F satisfies the given conditions (1) and (2). By taking x = y in the condition (1), it can be seen that 1 ∈ F. Let x, y ∈ X be such that x, x∗ y ∈ F. Then by the condition (2), we get y = 1 ∗ y = ((x∗ y) ∗ (x∗ y)) ∗ y = (x ∗ ((x ∗ y) ∗ y)) ∗ y ∈ F. Therefore F is a filter in X. □

For any congruence θ on a BE-algebra (X, ∗, 1), let us recall that the set X/θ of all congruence classes forms a BE-algebra with respect to the operation [x]θ ∗ [y]θ = [x ∗ y]θ for all x, y ∈ X. It also forms a partially ordered set ordered by set inclusion. The smallest congruence on X is given by θ0 = {(a, a) | a ∈ X}.

In the following, we first introduce two operations.

Definition 3.2. Let θ be a congruence on a BE-algebra X. Define operations α and β as follows:

(1) For any filter F of X, define α(F) = { [x]θ | (x, y) ∈ θ for some y ∈ F }

(2) For any filter of X/θ, define β() = {x ∈ X | (x, y) ∈ θ for some [y]θ ∈ }.

In the following lemma, some basic properties of the above two operations α and β are observed.

Lemma 3.3. Let θ be a congruence on a BE-algebra X. Then we have

(1) For any filter F of X, α(F) is a filter of X/θ,

(2) For any filter of L/θ, β() is a filter of X,

(3) α and β are isotone,

(4) For any filter F of X, x ∈ F implies [x]θ ∈ α(F),

(5) For any filter of X/θ, [x]θ ∈ implies x ∈ β().

Proof. (1). Let [x]θ ∈ X/θ and [a]θ ∈ α(F). Then (a, y) ∈ θ for some y ∈ F. Hence (x ∗ a, x ∗ y) ∈ θ and x ∗ y ∈ F because of F is a filer. Thus [x]θ ∗ [a]θ = [x ∗ a]θ ∈ α(F). Let [a]θ, [b]θ ∈ α(F). Then (a, x) ∈ θ and (b, y) ∈ θ for some x, y ∈ F. Now, for any t ∈ X, we get

Since x, y ∈ F and F is a filter, we get by Theorem 3.1 that (x ∗ (y ∗ t)) ∗ t ∈ F. Hence

Therefore by Theorem 3.1, it concludes that α(F) is a filter of X/θ.

(2). Let x ∈ X and a ∈ β(). Then (a, y) ∈ θ for some [y]θ ∈ . Hence (x ∗ a, x ∗ y) ∈ θ. Since is a filter, we get [x ∗ a]θ = [x ∗ y]θ = [x]θ ∗ [y]θ ∈ . Thus it yields x ∗ a ∈ β(). Again, let a, b ∈ β() and t ∈ X. Then we get (a, x) ∈ θ and (b, y) ∈ θ for some [x]θ ∈ and [y]θ ∈ . Since is a filter, we get [(x∗(y ∗t))∗t]θ = ([x]θ ∗([y]θ ∗[t]θ))∗[t]θ ∈ . Since (a, x) ∈ θ and (b, y) ∈ θ, it is clear that ((a ∗ (b ∗ t)) ∗ t, (x ∗ (y ∗ t)) ∗ t) ∈ θ. Since [(x ∗ (y ∗ t)) ∗ t]θ ∈ , we get (a ∗ (b ∗ t)) ∗ t ∈ β(). Therefore by Theorem 3.1, β() is a filter of X.

(3). Let F1, F2 be two filters in X such that F1 ⊆ F2. Let [x]θ ∈ α(F1). Then, we get (x, y) ∈ θ for some y ∈ F1 ⊆ F2. Consequently, we get that [x]θ ∈ α(F2). Therefore α(F1) ⊆ α(F2). Again, let be two filters of X/θ such that . Suppose x ∈ . Then, it infers that (x, y) ∈ θ for some [y]θ ∈ . Hence y ∈ . Therefore .

(4). For any x ∈ F, we have (x, x) ∈ θ. Hence it concludes [x]θ ∈ α(F).

(5). For any [x]θ ∈ , we have (x, x) ∈ θ. Hence we get x ∈ β(). □

The following corollary is a direct consequence of the above lemma.

Corollary 3.4. Let θ be a congruence on a BE-algebra X. Then we have

(1) For any normal filter F of X, α(F) is a normal filter of X/θ.

(2) For any normal filter of L/θ, β() is a normal filter of X.

Lemma 3.5. Let θ be a congruence on a BE-algebra X. For any filter F of X, αβα(F) = α(F).

Proof. Let [x]θ ∈ α(F). Then (x, y) ∈ θ for some y ∈ F. Since y ∈ F, by Lemma 3.3(4), we get [y]θ ∈ α(F). Since (x, y) ∈ θ and [y]θ ∈ α(F), we get x ∈ βα(F). Hence [x]θ ∈ αβα(F). Thus α(F) ⊆ αβα(F). Conversely, let [x]θ ∈ αβα(F). Then (x, y) ∈ θ for some y ∈ βα(F). Since y ∈ βα(F), there exists [a]θ ∈ α(F) such that (y, a) ∈ θ. Hence [x]θ = [y]θ = [a]θ ∈ α(F). Therefore αβα(F) ⊆ α(F).

We now intend to show that the composition βα is a closure operator on the set Ƒ(X) of all filters of a BE-algebra X.

Proposition 3.6. For any filter F of X, the map F → βα(F) is a closure operator on Ƒ(X). That is, for any two filters F, G of X, we have the following:

(a) F ⊆ βα(F).

(b) βαβα(F) = βα(F).

(c) F ⊆ G ⇒ βα(F) ⊆ βα(G).

Proof. (a). Let x ∈ F. Then by Lemma 3.3(4), we get [x]θ ∈ α(F). Since (x, x) ∈ θ and α(F) is a filter in X/θ, we get x ∈ βα(F). Therefore F ⊆ βα(F). (b). Since βα(F) is a filter in X, by above condition (a), we get βα(F) ⊆ βα[βα(F)]. Conversely, let x ∈ βα[βα(F)]. Then we obtain (x, y) ∈ θ for some [y]θ ∈ αβα(F). Thus by above Lemma 3.5, we get that [y]θ ∈ α(F). Hence x ∈ βα(F). Therefore, it concludes βα[βα(F)] ⊆ βα(F).

(c). Suppose F,G are two filters of X such that F ⊆ G. Let x ∈ βα(F). Then we get [x]θ ∈ α(F). Hence [x]θ = [y]θ for some y ∈ F ⊆ G. Since y ∈ G, we get [x]θ = [y]θ ∈ α(G). Therefore x ∈ βα(G). Hence βα(F) ⊆ βα(G). □ 0

Denoting by Ƒ(X/θ) the set of all filters of X/θ, we can therefore define a mapping α : Ƒ(X) → Ƒ(X/θ) by F ↦ α(F) also another mapping β : Ƒ(X/θ) → Ƒ(X) by F ↦ α(F). Then we have the following:

Proposition 3.7. Let θ be congruence on a BE-algebra X. Then α is a resid-uated map with residual map β.

Proof. For every F ∈ Ƒ(X), by Proposition 3.6(a), we have that F ⊆ βα(F). Let F ∈ Ƒ(X/θ). Suppose [x]θ ∈ F. Then we get x ∈ β(F). Since β(F) is a filter of X, we get [x]θ ∈ αβ(F). Hence, it yields F ⊆ αβ(F). Conversely, let [x]θ ∈ αβ(F). Then [x]θ = [y]θ for some y ∈ β(F). Since y ∈ β(F), we get [x]θ = [y]θ ∈ F. Hence αβ(F) ⊆ F. Therefore for every F ∈ Ƒ(X/θ), we obtain that αβ(F) = F. Since α and β are isotone, it follows that α is residuated and that the residual of α is nothing but β. □

We now introduce the notion of θ-filters in a BE-algebra.

Definition 3.8. Let θ be a congruence on a BE-algebra X. A filter F of X is called a θ-filter if βα(F) = F.

For any congruence θ on a BE-algebra X, it can be easily observed that the filter {1} is a θ-filter if and only if [1]θ = {1}. Moreover, we have the following:

Lemma 3.9. Let θ be a congruence on a bounded BE-algebra X with smallest element 0. For any filter F of X, the following hold:

(1) If F is a θ-filter then [1]θ ⊆ F, (2) If F is a proper θ-filter then F ∩[0]θ = ∅.

In the following theorem, a set of sufficient conditions is derived for a proper filter of a BE-algebra to become a θ-filter.

Theorem 3.10. Let θ be a congruence on a BE-algebra X. A proper filter F of X is a θ-filter if it satisfies the following conditions:

(1) For x, y ∈ X with x≠ y, either x ∈ F or y ∈ F

(2) To each x ∈ F, there exists x′ ∉ F such that (x, x′) ∈ θ

Proof. Let F be a proper filter of X. Clearly F ⊆ βα(F). Conversely, let x ∈ βα(F). Then (x, y) ∈ θ for some [y]θ ∈ α(F). Hence [y]θ = [a]θ for some a ∈ F. Since a ∈ F, there exists a′ ∉ F such that (a, a′) ∈ θ. Since (x, y) ∈ θ, (y, a) ∈ θ and (a, a′) ∈ θ, by the transitive property, we get (x, a′) ∈ θ. Since a′ ∉ F, by conditions (1) and (2), we get x ∈ F. Therefore βα(F) = F. □

We now characterize θ-filters in the following:

Theorem 3.11. Let θ be a congruence on a BE-algebra X. For any filter F of X, the following conditions are equivalent:

(1) F is a θ-filter; (2) For any x, y ∈ X, [x]θ = [y]θ and x ∈ F imply that y ∈ F; (3) (4) x ∈ F implies [x]θ ⊆ F.

Proof. (1) ⇒ (2): Assume that F is a θ-filter of X. Let x, y ∈ X be such that [x]θ = [y]θ. Then (x, y) ∈ θ. Suppose x ∈ F = βα(F). Then (x, a) ∈ θ for some [a]θ ∈ α(F). Thus (a, y) ∈ θ and [a]θ ∈ α(F). Therefore y ∈ βα(F) = F.

(2) ⇒ (3): Assume the condition (2). Let x ∈ F. Since x ∈ [x]θ, we get F ⊆ . Conversely, let a ∈ . Then (a, x) ∈ θ for some x ∈ F. Hence [a]θ = [x]θ. By the condition (2), we get a ∈ F. Therefore F = .

(3) ⇒ (4): Assume the condition (3). Let a ∈ F. Then we get that (x, a) ∈ θ for some x ∈ F. Let t ∈ [a]θ. Then (t, a) ∈ θ. Hence (x, t) ∈ θ. Thus it yields t ∈ [x]θ ⊆ F. Therefore it can be concluded that [a]θ ⊆ F.

(4) ⇒ (1): Assume the condition (4). Clearly F ⊆ βα(F). Conversely, let x ∈ βα(F). Then (x, y) ∈ θ for some [y]θ ∈ α(F). Hence [y]θ = [a]θ for some a ∈ F. Since a ∈ F, by condition (4), we get that x ∈ [y]θ = [a]θ ⊆ F. Thus βα(F) ⊆ F. Therefore F is a θ-filter of X. □

In the following theorem, a set of equivalent conditions is obtained to characterize the smallest congruence in terms of θ-filters of BE-algebra.

Theorem 3.12. Let θ be a congruence on a self-distributive BE-algebra X. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

(1) θ is the smallest congruence;

(2) Every filter is a θ-filter;

(3) Every principal filter is a θ-filter.

Proof. (1) ⇒ (2): Assume that θ is the smallest congruence on X. Let F be a filter of X and x ∈ F. Let t ∈ [x]θ. Then (t, x) ∈ θ. Hence t = x ∈ F. Thus we get [x]θ ⊆ F. Therefore by above Theorem 3.11, F is a θ-filter.

(2) ⇒ (3): It is obvious.

(3) ⇒ (1): Assume that every principal filter is a θ-filter. Let x, y ∈ X be such that (x, y) ∈ θ. Then [x]θ = [y]θ. Since ⟨y⟩ is a θ-filter, we get x ∈ [x]θ = [y]θ ⊆ ⟨y⟩. Since X is self-distributive, we get y ∗ x = 1. Hence y ≤ x. Similarly, we get x ≤ y. Hence x = y. Therefore θ is the smallest congruence. □

Finally, this article is concluded by obtaining a bijection between the set of all θ-filters of a BE-algebra and the set of all filters of its quotient algebra.

Theorem 3.13. Let θ be a congruence on a BE-algebra X. Then there exists a bijection between the set Ƒθ(X) of all θ-filters of X and the set of all filters of the BE-algebra X/θ of all congruence classes.

Proof. Define a mapping ψ : Ƒθ(X) ↦ Ƒ(X/θ) by ψ(F) = α (F) for all F ∈ Ƒθ(X). Let F,G ∈ Ƒθ(X). Then ψ(F) = ψ(G) ⇒ α(F) = α(G) ⇒ βα(F) = βα(G) ⇒ F = G(since F,G ∈ Ƒθ(X)). Hence ψ is one-one. Again, let be a filter of Ƒ(X/θ). Then β() is a filter in X. We now show that β() is a θ-filter in X. We have always β() ⊆ βαβ(). Let x ∈ βαβ(). Then we get (x, y) ∈ θ for some [y]θ ∈ αβ() = . Hence x ∈ β(). Therefore β() = βαβ(). Now for this β() ∈ X, we get ψ[β()] = αβ() = . Therefore ψ is onto. Therefore ψ is a bijection between Ƒθ(X) and Ƒ(X/θ). □

참고문헌

  1. S.S. Ahn, Y.H. Kim and J.M. Ko, Filters in commutative BE-algebras, Commun. Korean. Math. Soc., 27 (2012), 233-242. https://doi.org/10.4134/CKMS.2012.27.2.233
  2. S.S. Ahn and Y.H. So, On ideals and upper sets in BE-algebras, Sci. Math. Jpn., 68 (2008), 279-285.
  3. S.S. Ahn and K.S. So, On generalized upper sets in BE-algebras, Bull. Korean Math. Soc., 46 (2009), 281-287. https://doi.org/10.4134/BKMS.2009.46.2.281
  4. K. Iseki and S. Tanaka, An introduction to the theory of BCK-algebras, Math. Japon., 23 (1979), 1-26.
  5. H.S. Kim and Y.H. Kim, On BE-algebras, Sci. Math. Jpn., 66 (2007), 113-116.
  6. Y.H. Kim, On medial B-algebras, J. Appl. Math. & Informatics, 32 (2014), 849-856. https://doi.org/10.14317/jami.2014.849
  7. J.H. Park and Y.H. Kim, Int-soft positive implicative filters in BE-algebras, J. Appl. Math. & Informatics, 33 (2015), 459-467. https://doi.org/10.14317/jami.2015.459
  8. M. Sambasiva Rao, Multipliers and normal filters of BE-algebras, J. Adv. Res. Pure Math., 4 (2012), 61-67. https://doi.org/10.5373/jarpm.1088.083011
  9. K.S. So and Y.H. Kim, Mirror d-algebras, J. Appl. Math. & Informatics, 31 (2013), 559-564. https://doi.org/10.14317/jami.2013.559
  10. A. Walendziak, On normal filters and congruence relations in B-algebras, Commenta-tiones Mathematicae, 52 (2012), 199-205.